I continue to look at the rhetoric around aphantasia, or not having a mind's eye. Part 1 is here. Now I'm looking at two papers written before the word "aphantasia" was coined. Both recognize that some people do have mental pictures (minds eye type stuff) and that some people don't, which involves recognizing some level of cognitive diversity. What people then do with the knowledge is another story. Galton is known for eugenics, after all.
This paper is cited as being the first place where aphantasia is described. Galton had no problem calling it a mental deficiency (unlike the folks who coined the term in 2015; Faw refers to it a dis-ability in describing his own experience in 2009 and gets cited in 2015):
Appreciate my writing? Support me on Patreon!
So I'm starting with Bill Faw's paper, "Conflicting Intuitions May Be Based on Differing Abilities," which looks at the history of psychological/philosophical thought about mental imagery or the lack thereof. He points out a tendency for people to assume that everyone does this imagery (or doesn't do this imagery) the way the researcher them-self does(n't) do it. By and large, researchers assume it's a thing: most people can visualize things, after all. Faw
claims, “Much of the current imaging literature either denies the
existence of wakeful non-mental imagers, views non-imagers
motivationally as 'repressors' or 'neurotic', or acknowledges them
but does not fully incorporate them into their models.”
Faw
argues that the everyone uses mental images camp (thanks Aristotle) comes from two things: most people have mental images, and people tend to assume that what they do is what everyone does. Which leads me to ask regarding mental imagery what I've
asked before regarding autism: theory of whose mind?
(Sam mentions the incident in his thesis and on his blog.) Also, Faw
is himself aphantasiac, or a non-mental-imager, as he calls it in his
paper. (He's writing before the word aphantasia was coined. I kind of
want to check if he's written on the topic since.) He describes
reactions of disbelief from others, that non-imaging is even a thing,
as well as challenges to the notion that he could know this about
himself. Hello, parallels to autism with the “you can't know what
it's like you be yourself” thing.
It
does make skeptical sense to question whether people filling out a 5-
or 7-scale survey all mean the same by ‘vague and dim’! But it
seems untoward to dispute such strong statements of mental imaging
abilities — and the lack thereof — as seen in the self-reports
that Galton and I and many others have elicited. (16 in the
ResearchGate PDF, probably
60 in the actual journal)
And
that's the thing: I don't think people all mean the same thing by
vague, dim, vivid, or any other inherently subjective descriptor. I (and Faw) do think there's a clear difference between "vivid" and "non-existent," though. Enough of a difference that assuming that everyone does (or doesn't do) mental imagery the same way seems ... less than logical? But it's something quite a few philosophers and psychologists seem to have been doing along the way.
Aristotle assumes “normal” thought involves imagery. (What the
heck is normal? Hi, neurodiversity paradigm, it'd be nice to see you here.) Hobbes isn't talking
about pictures so specifically, but does seem to hold that
thinking/imagination depends on internal sensory creations. Locke
writes of memory as re-experiencing or re-creating prior perceptions
with the knowledge of having had them before. That's probably what my
intro to neurobiology teacher meant by vivid recall, and it's not a
thing I do except with sounds. Titchener describes his own mental
imagery as a gallery and can not conceive of even small gaps in the
streams of others imagery, assuming that his own experience is
universal. (Theory of whose mind?) He was actually one of the
respondents to Galton's survey, and he challenges the reports of
other respondents who don't
experience mental imagery.
Then
he turns to the opposite intuition, where someone who describes what
sounds like their own
experience without conscious mental imagery (Watson, in this case)
and assumes that this experience
is the one that generalizes. (Theory of whose mind?) He denies mental
imagery as being important to anyone
and questions its very existence for most. And I do think
generalizing ones own experience is a reasonable way to make guesses
unless and until you get better information, but he's doing this in
the face of a whole lot of descriptions of mental imagery by/from/for
others. Interestingly, this guy was one of the big definers of
behaviorist thought, and he claims thought as internal speech.
(My thought is usually internal speech, but sometimes it's
externalized typing or handwriting. Sometimes it's recognition of
patterns that I then need to somehow translate into language in one
of those forms.) That's the only person Faw describes as having
rejected the importance and possibly existence of mental imagery, and
even his descriptions of non-imaging are called ideological rejection
by folks who assume we all have mental pictures.
On a
similar note, Faw suggests (following Thomas Leahey) that Watson
might have been a strong auditory imager but weak or non- visual
imager. Which is a funny way of writing about it, since I always
thought imagery meant visual stuff, but there doesn't seem to be a
word for any similar activity with the other senses. Now that's
a fun question – why don't
we have words for internally created sensory perceptions for hearing
or smell? We do have the idea of songs getting stuck in our heads, so
I don't think it's most people not having
those sorts of perceptions. Since I describe my own non-imagery as
“no minds eye” I would make a parallel description using the idea
of a minds ear, nose, or tongue, but that doesn't quite work with
tactile sensations.
Then
he gets into Galton. I actually read Galton's 1880 paper, and my
thoughts on it come next:
"They had a mental deficiency of which they were unaware, and naturally enough supposed that those who were normally endowed, were romancing." (302)Remember that this guy is one of the big eugenics guys. Of course, he found this was most common in "men of science" and therefore had some motivation to find a reason that this was OK. Or not genetic, instead caused by disuse. Or both.
"Scientific men as a class have feeble powers of visual representation. There is no doubt whatever on the latter point, however it may be accounted for. My own conclusion is, that an over-readiness to perceive clear mental pictures is antagonistic to the acquirement of habits of highly generalised and abstract thought, and that if the faculty, of producing them was ever possessed by men who think hard, it is very apt to be lost by disuse ... I am however bound to say, that the missing faculty seems to be replaced so serviceably by other modes' of conception, chiefly I believe connected with the motor sense, that men who declare themselves entirely deficient in the power of seeing mental pictures can nevertheless give life-like descriptions of what they have seen, and can otherwise express themselves as if they were gifted with a vivid visual imagination." (304)That doesn't stop him from calling it a feeble ability or a mental deficiency, but he talks about compensation as not just a possibility, but as something that definitely happens.
But
what does Faw have to say about Galton? He points out that Galton's the one of the few who seems not to have assumed that his own experience of mental
imagery or lack thereof is everyone's
experience of mental imagery, and that this is good research. Which
is true enough. I still don't trust Galton as far as I can throw his
long-decayed corpse, because eugenics, but his thoughts on mental
imagery seem to be better balanced than the other folks Faw's been
reading.
George
Betts made a scale to measure visual imagery and looks around to see
how common aphantasia is. He finds 2% among his college students and
19% among other psychologists. Which means he, too, has to have
worked under the assumption that variation is a thing.
Then
we get more recent work which tries to check mental imagery
objectively rather than based on subjective self-reports, alongside
continued surveys of subjective reports that find people tending
towards “vivid” imagery. (Ok, but I'm still only understanding
vividness as a thing that I don't experience.) I assume that some of
the assumptions that internal imagery is required
for object recognition (I can do this), freehand drawing (I am
terrible at this), and spatial reasoning tasks (I'm good at these)
come into play with the supposedly objective measures, since Faw
described this sort of conflation as an issue in much of the
literature. Even Faw's eventual hypothesis of subliminal/unconscious
imagery that doesn't reach the conscious level still seems to be
working with the assumption that some sort of image-like process is
needed. It does recognize that it doesn't require an actual image,
which is nice (and which may
relate to Faw being aphantasiac himself and therefore knowing it's
possible!)
Works Cited
Faw, Bill. "Conflicting
intuitions may be based on differing abilities: Evidence from mental
imaging research." Journal of Consciousness Studies
16.4 (2009): 45-68.
Galton, Francis. "I.—Statistics
of mental imagery." Mind 19 (1880): 301-318.
Appreciate my writing? Support me on Patreon!