I read “Ethical Analysis of Neuroimaging in Alzheimer’s Disease.” J. Illes, A.Rosen, M. Greicius, and E. Racine. NIH Public Access manuscript,
eventually in Ann N Y Acad Sci2007 February under the title "Prospects for Prediction: Ethics Analysis of Neuroimaging in Alzheimer's Disease." My page numbers come from the NIH version, when I quote stuff.
Anyone else bothered by the consistent
framing where we demonstrate the significance of disability related
research by citing a significant/increasing “public health burden” and the money spent on care?
Anyone? (Fellow citizens, that is your money too.)
Now we're going to focus on ethical
issues around imaging/detection. (Which, I note, remain ethical
issues surrounding imaging/detection whether or not
you talk about public health burden and money!!!)
The
“Roles for current imaging capabilities” section seems to take it
as a given that identifying risk factors (for this thing we really
can't treat that well) in order to predict who's going to get
Alzheimer’s before they get it is important. I would have expected
that to be one of the ethical issues to discuss: do we identify folks
who are going to develop Alzheimer’s even though there's not really
a way to change this? (And that's at the 100% certainty level, which,
to be clear, is not current reality.
We can't predict who will/won't experience this. We can't predict
what cognitive changes a person will (or won't) experience as they
age with anywhere near that level of certainty.)
(Yes,
I think with something that would fall under the neurodiversity paradigm. Also cognitive liberty or freedom – people being in
charge of their own minds while also valuing diversity on a societal
level! I'm still inclined to treat neurological things that
will eventually kill you as
things I would like us to know how to change or prevent, because
death. And Alzheimer’s
will eventually kill you. Cognitive freedom also goes with “people
can choose what to do with their own minds” and “not dying of
dementia” is a common preference, let us science so people can make
that choice.)
Ah,
yes, good, stigma is getting addressed.
- Predictive imaging may expand the pool of disease to people who are much younger, and therefore expand the pool that is stigmatized.
- Both earlier prediction and stigma have the potential to reduce quality of life, including autonomy and the privilege to drive, and other daily functions.
- There may be medical discrimination against people at risk, for example, with respect to eligibility for organ transplantation. (4)
My
preference is for not stigma at all. Expanding the stigmatized pool
is not doing this. Neither is reducing it. Both of those are justmoving the line of acceptable minds around. Nope. (Still don't like
shoving people unwittingly or unwillingly into a stigmatized
population.)
It's
important to point out the quality of life issues where being in a
stigmatized group, all on its own, causes problems. Because it does.
Organ
transplant discrimination is a thing. I might not be able to get an
organ (autism, people get rejected for that all the time, sometimes
even when there's a family member willing to donate who isn't
offering this for anyone else re: kidney or liver.)
I
think we need to work on the stigma in addition to working with the
reality that it currently exists.
I
appreciate that “Scan everyone who wants a scan” is one of the
considered options. It gets the shortest discussion (probably because
“do for person X what person X wants” isn't that complicated) and
the issues brought up there are common to the other groups as well.
(Who should have access to the results of testing is not only
a question when the test was done without medical indication. It
might have different answers depending on the level of medical
indication for the test. I'm very much inclined towards “The person
who had the test decides who even knows the test took
place, and similarly who gets results.”
It's hard to coerce test results out of someone if you don't know
there's anything to coerce. The tricky thing is to make sure
employers can't coerce the test itself.) Unequal access remains an issue, but let's not pretend it's a non-issue for any of the other options.
I'm
betting the impact of results on personal liberty and similar closely
resemble the impacts of other known cognitive disabilities. Just a
hunch.
OH MY
GOD. NO. “the greater predictive power combined with the growing
number of people with AD might be the brick that breaks the back of
the current health care system. (6)” NO. YOU DO NOT PUT THE BLAME
FOR OUR MESSED UP SYSTEM EVENTUALLY BREAKING ON SICK OR DISABLED
PEOPLE. NO. NO. NO. YOU. DO. NOT. DO. THIS. Go yell at insurance
companies and congresspeople instead. NO. I hate you when you do this
nonsense with autism and I hate you when you do it with AD and just
generally hate it when you do this with the people who get screwed
over by the current system that really, really wants everyone to be
abled and to get briefly and treatably sick in ways that follow the textbook. And you know,
this idea that we're a burden on some system always, always
gets used to justify measures that reduce our personal liberties.
When you write things like this, you are part of the stigma
problem. Stop it.
(Try
instead “The current health care system is designed for XYZ and not
ABC. Given ABC, changes are needed.”)
The
incidental findings question. Yes, protocols being decided on for
these before the imaging. (Ulysses contract connection?)
“Much
remains to be learned about functional anomalities.” (8). Well.
Yes. We only seem to study this stuff when there's a perceived
deficit. If it's worked for the person their whole life, why would we
have noticed anything? [Hi, Galton the eugenicist deciding not totake issue with the lack of a minds eye because it seemed most commonin “men of science.” We're biased as heck about what unusual
things we decide are problems and what unusual things we decide to
study like the people who have them are objects.]